Cambridge University Press
978-0-521-84208-5 - Fallacies and Argument Appraisal - by Christopher W. Tindale
Frontmatter/Prelims



FALLACIES AND ARGUMENT APPRAISAL

Fallacies and Argument Appraisal presents an introduction to the nature, identification, and causes of fallacious reasoning, along with key questions for evaluation. Drawing from the latest work on fallacies as well as some of the standard ideas that have remained relevant since Aristotle, Christopher W. Tindale investigates central cases of major fallacies in order to understand what has gone wrong and why. Dispensing with the approach that simply assigns labels and brief descriptions, Tindale provides fuller treatments that recognize the dialectical and rhetorical contexts in which fallacies arise.

   This volume analyzes major fallacies through accessible, everyday examples. Critical questions are developed for each fallacy to help the student identify them and provide considered evaluations.

Christopher W. Tindale is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Windsor in Canada. He is coeditor of the journal Informal Logic: Reasoning and Argumentation in Theory and Practice, author of Acts of Arguing: A Rhetorical Model of Argument and Rhetorical Argumentation, and coauthor of Good Reasoning Matters, third edition.





CRITICAL REASONING AND ARGUMENTATION

General Editors
Douglas Walton, University of Winnipeg
Hans V. Hansen, University of Windsor

This series is aimed at introductory students in the field of argumentation, informal logic, and critical thinking. Informed by research in linguistics, communication, artificial intelligence, and pragmatics, as well as philosophy, books in this series are up to date in method and presentation, particularly in their emphasis on dialogue and rhetoric, which contrasts with the traditional “go it alone” approach. Each book is designed for use in a one-semester course and includes exercises.





FALLACIES AND ARGUMENT APPRAISAL

Christopher W. Tindale
University of Windsor





CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo

Cambridge University Press
32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10013–2473, USA

www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521842082

© Christopher W. Tindale 2007

This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without
the written permission of Cambridge University Press.

First published 2007

Printed in the United States of America

A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Tindale, Christopher W. (Christopher William)
Fallacies and argument appraisal / Christopher W. Tindale.
p. cm. – (Critical reasoning and argumentation)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-521-84208-5 (hardback) – ISBN 0-521-60306-4 (pbk.)
1. Fallacies (Logic) 2. Reasoning. I. Title. II. Series.
BC175.T56 2007
165–dc22   2006014059

ISBN-13 978-0-521-84208-2 hardback
ISBN-13 978-0-521-60306-5 paperback

Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for
the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or
third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such
Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.





For Jonathan





Contents

Preface page xiii
1 INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF FALLACIOUSNESS 1
  1. Strong and Weak Arguments 1
  2. Some Historical Conceptions of Fallacy 6
  3. Approaching Fallacies 12
  4. Why Arguments Go Wrong and How They Fool Us 14
  5. Avoiding Fallacious Reasoning 16
  6. Summary 16
     FURTHER READING 17
2 FALLACIES OF DIVERSION 19
  1. Straw Man 19
  2. Treatments of the Straw Man 25
  3. Red Herring 28
  4. What Has Gone Wrong in These Examples? Where Does the Fallacy Lie? 30
  5. Treatment and Evaluation of the Red Herring 32
  6. Irrelevant Conclusion 34
     Chapter Exercises 36
     Further Reading 40
3 FALLACIES OF STRUCTURE 41
  1. Invalid Structures 41
  2. Fallacies of Distribution 44
  3. Propositional Fallacies 49
  4. Treatments of Propositional Fallacies 50
  5. Formal and Informal Fallacies 52
     Chapter Exercises 54
     Further Reading 55
4 PROBLEMS WITH LANGUAGE 57
  1. Introduction 57
  2. Ambiguity and Equivocation 58
  3. Treatments of the Fallacy of Equivocation 62
  4. Vagueness 64
  5. Treatments of Vagueness 67
  6. Complex Question 69
  7. Treatment of Complex Question 71
  8. Begging the Question 72
  9. Treatments of Begging the Question 75
     Chapter Exercises 77
     Further Reading 80
5 AD HOMINEM ARGUMENTS 81
  1. Introduction 81
  2. The General Ad Hominem 83
  3. Treatments of Ad Hominem 86
  4. Types of Ad Hominem 92
     Chapter Exercises 97
     Further Reading 102
6 OTHER ‘AD’ ARGUMENTS 104
  1. Introduction 104
  2. Argumentum Ad Populum 105
  3. Argumentum Ad Baculum 108
  4. Argumentum Ad Misericordiam 113
  5. Argumentum Ad Ignorantiam 117
  6. Summary 121
     Chapter Exercises 121
     Further Reading 126
7 THE AD VERECUNDIAM AND THE MISUSE OF EXPERTS 127
  1. Introduction 127
  2. Authorities and Experts 128
  3. Testimony 130
  4. The General Appeal to an Expert 131
  5. Ways of Fallaciousness: Complexities of the Appeal 134
  6. Summary 143
     Chapter Exercises 144
     Further Reading 147
8 SAMPLING 149
  1. Introduction 149
  2. Generalizations 150
  3. Treatment of Generalization Fallacies 155
  4. Polls and Studies 159
  5. Fallacy of Insufficient Statistics 159
  6. Fallacy of Biased Statistics 161
  7. Measurement Errors 163
     Chapter Exercises 167
     Further Reading 171
9 CORRELATION AND CAUSE 173
  1. Correlations and Causal Reasoning 173
  2. The Post Hoc Fallacy 174
  3. Misidentifying the Cause 179
  4. The Argument from Consequences 183
  5. The Fallacy of the Slippery Slope 185
  6. Distinguishing Causal Slopes from Precedents 188
     Chapter Exercises 189
     Further Reading 193
10 ANALOGICAL REASONING 194
  1. Principles of Analogy 194
  2. False Analogy 196
  3. Fallacious Appeal to Precedent 201
  4. Two Wrongs by Analogy 205
     Chapter Exercises 208
     Further Reading 213
  Index 215





Preface

The philosophy of reasoning, to be complete, ought to comprise the theory of bad as well as of good reasoning.

– John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic

This latest addition to the Cambridge series in Critical Reasoning and Argumentation is a study of bad reasoning, principally as conveyed through traditional and modern fallacies. While the study of fallacies has a long and detailed history, the bulk of critical literature on the fallacies has appeared in the last three or four decades. So much that is new and interesting can be drawn into a full study of the fallacies. The rationale behind this volume is to introduce students to the study of fallacy by means of the latest research in the field, along with some of the standard ideas that have remained relevant since the time of Aristotle. Thus, each topic and fallacy is couched within a discussion of current thinking, providing the clearest explanation possible of both what goes wrong in some of the more prevalent patterns of fallacious reasoning and why arguers and audiences might be misled by such errors.

One thing the recent literature has made very clear is that fallacies are far more complex, and thus deserving of much fuller analyses, than the traditional textbook treatments have suggested. Too often, fallacies are assigned a label and a brief description, along with an admonition to students to avoid such mistakes in their own reasoning. Not only is this insufficient as a treatment of any fallacy, but such an approach also fails to raise the question of how fallacious reasoning might come about in the first place and why it might prove so deceptive. Two things have reinforced the recognition of how complex fallacies really are: The first of these is the appreciation, now fully expressed in the literature, that many of the fallacies are failed instances of good argument schemes or forms. Hence, we cannot dismiss all ad hominem arguments or Slippery Slopes, for example, because there are circumstances under which such reasoning is appropriate. What is required, then, is a careful review of the differences between good and bad instances of such schemes. The label/description approach does not allow for this. The second feature that reveals the complexity of fallacious reasoning is the recognition that to evaluate fallacies fully we need to consider aspects of the context in which the argumentation arises. In many instances this involves the details of a dialogue between participants in an argumentative exchange. In other cases we must sift through what is available of the background to a dispute, such as the history of exchanges between the participants or the beliefs of the audience. This brings into consideration dialectical and rhetorical features crucial to understanding and evaluating fallacies and shows that the study involves more than a traditional logical assessment of the propositions involved. It is also important to consider these features when asking how the fallacious reasoning can come about and prove so effective.

Appreciating this complexity further helps explain why we should study the fallacies at all. One response might be that we should simply ignore them, since they demonstrate failures of human reason and do not contribute to our important social debates. But it is because of these things that we are advised to be particularly alert to the presence and nature of fallacies. And if we are to do that, we should give them serious consideration and not relegate them to the status of minor topics touched on in passing. From my own perspective, this recognition has brought about a change of view. Although I was persuaded for a long time that the focus of the study of argumentation should be on good reasoning, the complexity of the fallacies and their interesting rhetorical features have convinced me that a more balanced treatment is important and that, as Mill reminds us, a complete appreciation of argumentation will involve accounts of both good and bad reasoning. The study of fallacies, then, is an important part of a whole approach to argumentation – the more so because it is so revealing of how we actually reason. As with many other activities in which we engage (like reading, writing, or calculation), the norm becomes so commonplace that we fail to notice it and learn from it. It is only when we are confronted with a breakdown of those norms that our attention is caught. In many ways fallacies are breakdowns of the norms of reasoning, and through their study we gain a better understanding of ourselves as reasoners and as members of audiences in social settings.

The approach taken to the fallacies in this book tries to match the seriousness and complexity presented in the foregoing paragraphs. This means in the first instance that I have tried as much as possible to illustrate the fallacies through cases of ordinary reasoning that can arise or have arisen in everyday contexts. We will see less of arguments expressed in just a few lines than of detailed reasoning embedded in larger contexts. The more broad contexts we provide and the more we say about them, the more we may be able to understand what has gone wrong and why. You will certainly find the examples in the exercises at the ends of the later chapters more detailed than some of those earlier in the book. This greater complexity reflects the expected growth of ability and understanding that students should develop as they work through the book. The examples that illustrate fallacies are also presented by means of cases, since cases have a history and a context, involve people, and have consequences. While we will develop principles for dealing with the fallacies studied, any instance or suspected instance of one should be treated as a unique case, assessed on its own terms, since not all ideas associated with a fallacy may apply to any particular case. In this respect, the treatments again reflect what will be encountered outside an academic setting.

Given the conciseness of the book and its introductory nature, some decisions have had to be made about which fallacies to include and which to exclude. In general, I have tried to include the most regularly occurring patterns of fallacious reasoning. A secondary consideration has been given to those that are important historically because of what they illustrate about the nature of fallacies and why people both commit and are deceived by them. The book is designed to work as a companion to Douglas Walton’s Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation, although it should also work with other good introductions to argumentation or in courses dedicated to the separate study of fallacies. The principal tool used to treat the fallacies is a set of Critical Questions for each. These questions are designed to help the reasoner think through the complexities of a given case, identifying what is at stake and what has gone wrong, and then focusing on the right features to provide a full evaluation.

This book would not have seen the light of day without the encouragement and interest of the late Terry Moore at Cambridge. I hope the final product reflects well as part of his legacy. He will be deeply missed.

My thinking about the fallacies and how they might best be treated has been influenced by a large number of people researching and writing in the field. The debts will be evident in the discussions and references of each chapter. I am particularly indebted to Douglas Walton and Hans V. Hansen for their work as editors of this series and for their own contributions to the understanding of fallacies, the influences of which will be apparent. I have also gained much from recent discussions and written exchanges with Andreas Welzel on the causes of fallacious reasoning and the nature of fallacies as norm violations. During periods of writing over the last few years I have benefited from interactions with a number of students, particularly those at Trent University in my senior seminar on the fallacies. Finally, my former assistant, Daniel Farr, researched many of the examples used in the body of chapters and in exercises. I was indeed fortunate to have had such interested and able help.





© Cambridge University Press